Löb's theorem
In mathematical logic, Löb's theorem states that in Peano arithmetic (PA) (or any formal system including PA), for any formula P, if it is provable in PA that "if P is provable in PA then P is true", then P is provable in PA. If Prov(P) means that the formula P is provable, we may express this more formally as
- If
- then
- .
An immediate corollary (the contrapositive) of Löb's theorem is that, if P is not provable in PA, then "if P is provable in PA, then P is true" is not provable in PA. For example, "If is provable in PA, then " is not provable in PA.[1]
Löb's theorem is named for Martin Hugo Löb, who formulated it in 1955.[2] It is related to Curry's paradox.[3]
Löb's theorem in provability logic
[edit]Provability logic abstracts away from the details of encodings used in Gödel's incompleteness theorems by expressing the provability of in the given system in the language of modal logic, by means of the modality . That is, when is a logical formula, another formula can be formed by placing a box in front of , and is intended to mean that is provable.
Then we can formalize Löb's theorem by the axiom
known as axiom GL, for Gödel–Löb. This is sometimes formalized by means of the inference rule:
- If
- then
- .
The provability logic GL that results from taking the modal logic K4 (or K, since the axiom schema 4, , then becomes redundant) and adding the above axiom GL is the most intensely investigated system in provability logic.
Modal proof of Löb's theorem
[edit]Löb's theorem can be proved within modal logic using only some basic rules about the provability operator (the K4 system) plus the existence of modal fixed points.
Modal formulas
[edit]We will assume the following grammar for formulas:
- If is a propositional variable, then is a formula.
- If is a propositional constant, then is a formula.
- If is a formula, then is a formula.
- If and are formulas, then so are , , , , and
A modal sentence is a formula in this syntax that contains no propositional variables. The notation is used to mean that is a theorem.
Modal fixed points
[edit]If is a modal formula with only one propositional variable , then a modal fixed point of is a sentence such that
We will assume the existence of such fixed points for every modal formula with one free variable. This is of course not an obvious thing to assume, but if we interpret as provability in Peano Arithmetic, then the existence of modal fixed points follows from the diagonal lemma.
Modal rules of inference
[edit]In addition to the existence of modal fixed points, we assume the following rules of inference for the provability operator , known as Hilbert–Bernays provability conditions:
- (necessitation) From conclude : Informally, this says that if A is a theorem, then it is provable.
- (internal necessitation) : If A is provable, then it is provable that it is provable.
- (box distributivity) : This rule allows you to do modus ponens inside the provability operator. If it is provable that A implies B, and A is provable, then B is provable.
Proof of Löb's theorem
[edit]Much of the proof does not make use of the assumption , so for ease of understanding, the proof below is subdivided to leave the parts depending on until the end.
Let be any modal sentence.
- Apply the existence of modal fixed points to the formula . It then follows that there exists a sentence such that
. - , from 1.
- , from 2 by the necessitation rule.
- , from 3 and the box distributivity rule.
- , by applying the box distributivity rule with and .
- , from 4 and 5.
- , from 6 by the internal necessitation rule.
- , from 6 and 7.
Now comes the part of the proof where the hypothesis is used. - Assume that . Roughly speaking, it is a theorem that if is provable, then it is, in fact true. This is a claim of soundness.
- , from 8 and 9.
- , from 1.
- , from 10 and 11.
- , from 12 by the necessitation rule.
- , from 13 and 10.
More informally, we can sketch out the proof as follows.
- Since by assumption, we also have , which implies .
- Now, the hybrid theory can reason as follows:
- Suppose is inconsistent, then PA proves , which is the same as .
- However, already knows that , a contradiction.
- Therefore, is consistent.
- By Godel's second incompleteness theorem, this implies is inconsistent.
- Thus, PA proves , which is the same as .
Examples
[edit]An immediate corollary of Löb's theorem is that, if P is not provable in PA, then "if P is provable in PA, then P is true" is not provable in PA. Given we know PA is consistent (but PA does not know PA is consistent), here are some simple examples:
- "If is provable in PA, then " is not provable in PA, as is not provable in PA (as it is false).
- "If is provable in PA, then " is provable in PA, as is any statement of the form "If X, then ".
- "If the strengthened finite Ramsey theorem is provable in PA, then the strengthened finite Ramsey theorem is true" is not provable in PA, as "The strengthened finite Ramsey theorem is true" is not provable in PA (despite being true).
In Doxastic logic, Löb's theorem shows that any system classified as a reflexive "type 4" reasoner must also be "modest": such a reasoner can never believe "my belief in P would imply that P is true", without also believing that P is true.[4]
Gödel's second incompleteness theorem follows from Löb's theorem by substituting the false statement for P.
Converse: Löb's theorem implies the existence of modal fixed points
[edit]Not only does the existence of modal fixed points imply Löb's theorem, but the converse is valid, too. When Löb's theorem is given as an axiom (schema), the existence of a fixed point (up to provable equivalence) for any formula A(p) modalized in p can be derived.[5] Thus in normal modal logic, Löb's axiom is equivalent to the conjunction of the axiom schema 4, , and the existence of modal fixed points.
Notes
[edit]- ^ Unless PA is inconsistent (in which case every statement is provable, including ).
- ^ Löb 1955.
- ^ Neel, Krishnaswami. "Löb's theorem is (almost) the Y combinator". Semantic Domain. Retrieved 9 April 2024.
- ^ Smullyan 1986.
- ^ Lindström 2006.
References
[edit]- Boolos, George S. (1995). The Logic of Provability. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-48325-4.
- Hinman, P. (2005). Fundamentals of Mathematical Logic. A K Peters. ISBN 978-1-56881-262-5.
- Japaridze, Giorgi; De Jongh, Dick (1998). "Chapter VII - The Logic of Provability". In Buss, Samuel R. (ed.). Handbook of Proof Theory. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. Vol. 137. Elsevier. pp. 475–546. doi:10.1016/S0049-237X(98)80022-0.
- Lindström, Per (June 2006). "Note on Some Fixed Point Constructions in Provability Logic". Journal of Philosophical Logic. 35 (3): 225–230. doi:10.1007/s10992-005-9013-8. S2CID 11038803.
- Löb, Martin (1955). "Solution of a Problem of Leon Henkin". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 20 (2): 115–118. doi:10.2307/2266895. JSTOR 2266895. S2CID 250348262.
- Smullyan, Raymond M. (1986). "Logicians who reason about themselves". Proceedings of the 1986 conference on Theoretical aspects of reasoning about knowledge, Monterey (CA). San Francisco (CA): Morgan Kaufmann Publishers Inc. pp. 341–352. doi:10.1016/B978-0-934613-04-0.50028-4. ISBN 9780934613040.
External links
[edit]- "Löb's theorem". 22 March 2013. PlanetMath. Retrieved 14 December 2023.
- "Provability Logic" entry by Rineke (L.C.) Verbrugge in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2017